Ellul 5.pdf

(126 KB) Pobierz
<!DOCTYPE html PUBLIC "-//W3C//DTD HTML 4.01//EN" "http://www.w3.org/TR/html4/strict.dtd">
10.1177/0270467604270259
BULLETIN OF SCIENCE, TECHNOLOGY & SOCIETY / December 2004
Son / THE TECHNOLOGICAL BLUFF
Reading Jacques Ellul’s
The Technological Bluff in Context
Wha-Chul Son
Katholieke Universiteit Leuven
This article is a critical review of The Technologi-
cal Bluff , the last book on technology by Jacques Ellul.
Although this work has attracted little attention, the
concept of techno-logical bluff 1 provides a new per-
spective to understand contemporary technological
society. After presenting Ellul’s exposition of the con-
cept of techno-logical bluff, its original contribution to
technology studies is emphasized. It is also examined
how the analysis of techno-logical bluff is connected
with other major Ellulian notions such as autonomous
technique and the efficiency principle. This is followed
by a suggestion that the analysis of techno-logical
bluff could function as a basis for a constructive dia-
lectic relationship between classical and more recent
discourses on technology. The last section is devoted
to the Ellulian solution for the technological society
suggested in this work, namely, the paradox of
nonfreedom.
title The Technological Bluff ” (Karim, 2001, p. 131,
note 3). Ellul himself, however, claims the novelty of
TB’s project. He says that “some think that this book
of mine cannot hope to say anything new. Neverthe-
less, I see some important things that have not yet been
brought to light” (TB, p. xii).
The purpose of this article is to clarify the concept
of the techno-logical bluff 2 and to examine whether TB
provides a new perspective to understand contempo-
rary technological society. Has Ellul said anything
new by introducing the new concept, techno-logical
bluff? What is its contribution to Ellul’s own idea and
how does it differ from, for example, propaganda?
How different is his view on the technological society
in the late 1980s from the one of the 1950s and how is it
incorporated in this work?
Apart from Ellul’s own comment, there are at least
three other reasons for assuming that it is worthwhile
to read TB closely. First, during the intermediate pe-
riod between TSys and TB, there was “an explosion of
techniques” (TB, p. 1) that is now in its full-fledged
stage. Ellul witnessed information technology, com-
munication technology and bio-technology, albeit on a
far less developed level. It would be interesting to see
what the master of classical philosophy of technology
has to say about these new technologies that other phi-
losophers of technology such as Martin Heidegger,
Herbert Marcuse, and Lewis Mumford, who are often
associated with Ellul, could not yet have experienced.
Another reason is that the generally negative, critical,
and more abstract trend of philosophy of technology
before the 1960s has changed into more diverse voices
during the 1980s. If Ellul is taken as representing the
old regime, then one might expect some reaction to re-
cent discussions in philosophy of technology. Third,
reading TB can help us to understand this difficult
author a bit more clearly. Vanderburg (1998) said,
Keywords: technology; techno-logical bluff; auton-
omy of technique; principle of efficiency; paradox of
nonfreedom; propaganda; Herbert Marcuse; Jacques
Ellul
T he Technological Bluff (1988/1990; from here on,
TB) is the last book on technology by Ellul following
The Technological Society (1954/1964; from here on,
TSoc) and The Technological System (1977/1980;
from here on, TSys). Compared with many of his other
books including more theological ones, however, TB
has attracted little attention. Many articles have been
published about Ellul’s works and ideas since TB was
published; however, only a few have mentioned this
work, most of them only in passing, some of them with
obvious misunderstanding and contempt. 2
One commentator even said that Ellul “rewrote and
expanded that book [TSoc] and published it under the
Bulletin of Science, Technology & Society, Vol. 24, No. 6, December 2004, 518-533
DOI: 10.1177/0270467604270259
Copyright
2004 Sage Publications
Son / THE TECHNOLOGICAL BLUFF
519
Each work [of Ellul] has too much of its own
independent intellectual existence. I would
argue that each article and book relates to the
whole of his work more like a holographic plate
that has been cut into pieces. Illuminating each
piece in an appropriate manner reveals the entire
image. (p. 77)
term, for example, “systematic inquiry of technique”
or “invention, development and cognitive deployment
of tools and other artifacts,” as Hickman (2001, pp. 11-
12) suggests in his definition of technology. Whereas
Hickman’s notions of technology are more closely
related to the actual deployment of technique, dis-
course on technique could mean “what people think
about technique” or even the philosophy or sociology
of technique (TB, p. xv).
Accordingly, the project of TB is different from
those of TSoc and TSys in the sense that TB focused
on the discourse that sustains technological society
and technological system, not on the phenomenon of
techniques itself. In other words, the prime concern of
TB was, for example, not whether technology is auton-
omous, but how and why people come to view technol-
ogy being completely under the control of human
beings.
In the remainder of this section, I elaborate the
notion of techno-logical bluff further by presenting
Ellul’s own exposition and comparing it with similar
concepts and approaches in philosophy of technology.
Although having been constantly accused of being a
pessimist, Ellul still wrote another book on technolog-
ical society. This manifests that he has not given up the
hope for a better future. TB might help to figure out the
entire image of Ellul’s thought on technology by re-
vealing its unique illumination.
In the following, I begin with Ellul’s exposition of
the concept of techno-logical bluff as well as its origi-
nal contribution to the interpretation of our age. To
clarify this concept, I compare techno-logical bluff
with Ellul’s own analysis of propaganda and Herbert
Marcuse’s theory of the “one-dimensional man.” Then
I demonstrate how this concept is consistent with
major Ellulian notions that were suggested 2 decades
ago: autonomous technique and the efficiency princi-
ple. This will be followed by an observation of how the
analysis of the techno-logical bluff could provide cri-
teria for examining more recent theories in technology
studies. 3 Although these elucidations reveal that
Ellul’s view on contemporary technological society is
not brighter than his previous analysis in TSoc, the last
section is devoted to the Ellulian solution in terms of
the paradox of freedom presented in TB.
The Phenomenon of Techno-logy Bluff
Ellul explains what he means by techno-logical
bluff as follows.
I am not referring to technical bluff. I am not try-
ing to show that techniques do not deliver what
they promise, that technicians are bluffers. ...I
am talking about technological bluff, about the
gigantic bluff in which discourse on techniques
envelops us, making us believe anything and, far
worse, changing our whole attitude to tech-
niques: the bluff of politicians, the bluff of the
media, the bluff of technicians when they talk
about technique instead of working at them, the
bluff of publicity, the bluff of economic models.
(TB, p. xvi)
Understanding the
Concept of Techno-logy Bluff
Technique and Techno-Logy
What does Ellul mean by techno-logical bluff and
why does it matter? To answer these questions, one has
to first figure out the difference between technique and
techno-logy in Ellul’s philosophy of technology.
Ellul emphasized the distinction between technique
( technique ) and techno-logy ( technologie ). Technique
refers to “the totality of methods rationally arrived at
and having absolute efficiency (for a given stage of
development) in every field of human activity” (TSoc,
p. xxv). It should also be noted that Ellul’s technique
mainly refers to modern techniques.
Ellul explained that techno-logy means the “dis-
course on technique” (TB, pp. xv-xvi). This has a
broader meaning than other possible definitions of the
The bluff (a) demonstrates “the prodigious power,
diversity, success, universal application, and impecca-
bility of techniques” (TB, p. xvi); (b) conceals nega-
tive aspects of technique, and eventually (c) intensifies
the relationship between human and machines (TB,
p. 16). As the result of the techno-logical bluff, tech-
nique is seen as the only chance for progress and devel-
opment in every society (TB, p. xvi). Here Ellul is ad-
dressing a problem that has been largely ignored in the
philosophy of technology. It is not a matter of concrete
520
BULLETIN OF SCIENCE, TECHNOLOGY & SOCIETY / December 2004
problems caused by techniques, but of how people
perceive technique and react to problems caused by it.
The techno-logical bluff makes those problems
invisible and thus obsolete.
The techno-logical bluff has many forms. It could
be as direct as an advertisement that begins with “tech-
nology is our future” but could also manifest itself via
technology policy, education, media, and so on. It also
refers to some hidden assumptions on which the adver-
tisement or policy is based. Ellul presented some spec-
imens of the techno-logical bluff such as (a) the dis-
course on humanism that claims that “all technical
activity orients us to a greater humanity” (TB, p. 125);
(b) the emphasis on technical culture that is a contra-
diction in terms, according to Ellul, because “tech-
nique is universal, whereas culture cannot be” (TB,
p. 144); (c) the assurance of human mastery over tech-
nique; (d) the claim for the power of rationality; (e) the
ideology of science as an inevitable and necessary
means of salvation; and (f) the trust in experts.
According to Ellul, the techno-logical bluff is a new
phenomenon that arose in the 1980s when what Ellul
called a “great innovation” took place (TB, pp. 16-23).
It was a silent transformation of the public perception
of technique. Before the 1980s, Ellul argued, people
had not adapted very well to the technological prog-
ress since the Industrial Revolution. There had been
many attempts to resolve the problem of people’s
maladaptation to the ever-changing technical environ-
ment. The pessimistic analysis of technique and opti-
mistic utopianism were different kinds of one effort
serving the same purpose. The great innovation refers
to the phenomenon that those expectations and disap-
pointments started fading away. The transformation
was simple. People stopped trying to resolve the prob-
lem but got used to it. “They have stopped trying to
clash head on with obstacles and refusals. They have
stopped trying to rectify technical malfunctioning by
direct action” (TB, p. 18). Problems caused by tech-
nique have come to be taken as ordinary and inevita-
ble. In other words, the techno-logical bluff is a new
mechanism through which the myth of technical
progress can continue to prevail in our contemporary
technological society.
sition, . . . and partly because it has an obvious
cogency that is not found on the part of what
might oppose it. . . . Ordinariness gives reassur-
ance. The genius of technique (not of techni-
cians) is to produce the most reassuring and
innocent ordinariness. This is what we are study-
ing under the title of the technological bluff. (TB,
pp. 18-19)
The effect of the techno-logical bluff is manifest in
two types of people in the technological society: the
fascinated and the diverted. Fascinated people marvel
at the continuous development of technology and trust
that technology will bring the ultimate good for hu-
manity, without any critical attitude. Diverted people
do not care what is going on but are constantly diverted
by unnecessary technological gadgets, sports, games,
movie stars, and so on. Consequently, there is no room
left for rational, critical, and free judgment that defines
humanity. Ellul diagnosed the situation as “the
triumph of the absurd” (TB, p. 199).
This analysis might seem to be counterintuitive
because it is common to see critical attitude develop-
ing among large groups of citizens toward aspects of
the technological society. For example, since the
1980s, environmental movement has been quite suc-
cessful. More recently antiglobalization movement
could also be seen as a counterexample. This criticism
is not or only partly justifiable, as we see in the later
part of this article.
Characteristics of Techno-logy Bluff
How different is the analysis of the techno-logical
bluff from Ellul’s previous works and other thinkers
critical about technology? This section is devoted to
elucidate the original contribution of TB, by compar-
ing characteristics of the techno-logical bluff with
similar concepts and ideas.
Techno-logical bluff and propaganda . First of all,
as hinted above, techno-logical bluff itself is not a
technique. More specifically, techno-logical bluff
should be distinguished from propaganda or human
technique. Techno-logical bluff does not necessarily
contain a purposeful message similar to propaganda
and has a broader and deeper scope than the latter. The
techno-logical bluff spreads the vague and broad idea
that technique is the inevitable and unique source of
human betterment and progress, whereas propaganda
conveys a more defined message that is deliberately
Things are done . . . the proliferation of tech-
niques . . . has outflanked prior obstacles and
integrated them progressively into the pro-
cess. ...Ithasdone all this without any hostile
reaction or refusal, partly because what is pro-
posed infinitely transcends all capacity for oppo-
Son / THE TECHNOLOGICAL BLUFF
521
designed by some group of people. A simple remark of
a schoolteacher who emphasizes the importance of
science and technique or a speech of an activist who ar-
gues for more environment-friendly techniques, could
function as techno-logical bluff.
Two remarks must be made. First, this does not
mean that Ellul followed the simple definition of pro-
paganda as a mischievous manipulation of the public
on a very specific topic. In his earlier book, Propa-
ganda (1962/1965), Ellul presented an extensive anal-
ysis of propaganda revealing (a) that “integrating pro-
paganda” is more important than “agitation
propaganda” in the technological society (pp. 70-79),
(b) that the simple contrast of propagandist as deceiver
and propagandee as victim cannot be held because, in
modern technological society, propagandist and
propagandee need propaganda for their own sakes
(pp. 118-160), and (c) that propaganda aims to change
men’s attitude in a certain way (the subtitle of Propa-
ganda is The Formation of Men’s Attitude ), as one can
see in many indirect forms of propaganda such as com-
pany public relations (PR). However, the analysis of
Propaganda always presupposed the structure of pro-
pagandist and propagandee, which is not the case with
the techno-logical bluff the origin or shape of which
are varied.
Second, in spite of the difference, propaganda and
techno-logical bluff have a very close relationship in
two senses: (a) one of the most effective tools of
techno-logical bluff is propaganda. Commercial
advertisement (direct product commercial and indirect
company PR) and government propaganda are very
powerful in making people trust in technique. (b) To a
certain extent, technological bluff can be seen as the
result of various propaganda. Each propaganda has its
own message; however, as a whole, the propaganda
technique has contributed to the formation of men’s
attitude toward technique as a whole. The techno-
logical bluff is produced by those who have this trans-
formed attitude; yet it is not propaganda any more.
One could support Ellul’s claim by saying that propa-
ganda of technological society has led to the great
innovation since the 1980s, when the techno-logical
bluff began to prevail. Nakajima (2001) analyzed
green PR in terms of Ellul’s integration propaganda
revealing how green PR can change people’s attitude
toward a certain environmental issue, so that related
corporations can continue to benefit from their
antienvironmental products or activity. The effect,
however, is not limited to attitudes concerning a spe-
cific issue. Green PR, together with hundreds of other
kinds of propaganda, make technique in general, a
very ordinary and comfortable part of human life.
Because of this ordinariness of technique, many kinds
of techno-logical bluff are produced and reproduced,
without any deliberate designer.
Marcuse’s one-dimensional man and the techno-
logical bluff . Ellul’s analysis of techno-logical bluff
reminds us of Marcuse’s notion of one-dimensional
man. Marcuse argued in the 1960s that the advanced
industrial society had lost the dynamic of the preced-
ing period and the ability to accommodate critical
thoughts. Its system is rigidly institutionalized and has
a tendency to preserve the established existing struc-
ture. Consequently, individual freedom to criticize the
existing system and imagine something completely
new is suppressed by various mechanisms, such as
propaganda and cultural industries. According to
Marcuse, when man does not have the ability to tran-
scend and criticize standards and norms of the existing
society, he is one-dimensional man. The society that
does not allow potential alternatives to its system is a
one-dimensional society. While criticizing his con-
temporary society as one dimensional, however,
Marcuse also hinted that there could be a revolutionary
change initiated by outsiders of society and few
intelligentia (Kellner, 1991, p. xxxvi; Marcuse, 1964,
p. 256), and this prediction partially came to pass in the
May Events of 1968.
There are apparent similarities between Ellul’s and
Marcuse’s analysis, especially in terms of how citizens
of the technological society or advanced industrial
society suffer from a false image of the world. Both of
them analyze the system that makes impossible any
critical thinking and reflection, creates false needs,
and promotes a positive attitude toward the existing
structure of society.
Nevertheless, Ellul does not give any indication that
his analysis of techno-logical bluff is connected to
Marcuse’s theory. Instead, in his brief summary of the
history of the ideologies concerning science, Ellul
claimed that in the period between 1945 and 1975 sci-
ence was confronted with an ideological crisis.
According to him, people were not enthusiastic about
science. During that period, the close link between sci-
ence and technique, as well as the ambiguity about the
value and positive nature of science, were recognized
(TB, pp. 172-178). The image of science pursuing
truth and happiness, which had prevailed since the
18th century until 1945, was broken, and many skepti-
cal questions about science were raised. As Ellul’s
522
BULLETIN OF SCIENCE, TECHNOLOGY & SOCIETY / December 2004
own TSoc (1964) and Marcuse’s (1964) One Dimen-
sional Man were written in that period, one can specu-
late that Ellul viewed Marcuse’s insight as similar to
his TSoc and, thus, distinguished them from what he
wanted to convey in TB.
Ellul continued that, after 1975, corresponding to
the time of the aforementioned great innovation, the
ideological crisis has been reversed and science (and
technique) regains its respected status. The connection
between science and technique was not considered
negative, but positive, as it leads to economic benefit.
Furthermore, science, now indistinguishable from
technique, is viewed as something inevitable for
progress.
dialectical thinking operates (TSys, p. 318). It is a pro-
cess that is innate in modern technique, because of
which one eventually loses the external viewpoint.
Mentioning these two texts in relation with TB, Punzo
(1996) argued that “Ellul sees the great design of the
technological bluff as being directed to sealing human
life within this universe” (p. 25). 4
This reveals the fundamental difference between
Marcuse’s and Ellul’s ideas concerning the relation-
ship between modern technique, market, and politics.
Namely, while Ellul (1954/1964) argued that tech-
nique is the prime mover 5 of social, political, eco-
nomic, and cultural change (p. 133), Marcuse believed
that the problem of advanced industrial society and its
fascinated and diverted people is essentially a politico-
economical one. Marcuse (1964) stated, “Today polit-
ical power asserts itself through power over the ma-
chine process and over the technical organization of
the apparatus” (p. 3). The same position is held by
Horkheimer and Adorno (1969/2002):
More than ever, through the social transforma-
tion that it entails, science is becoming not
merely the discovering of nature but the response
to everything that disquiets or troubles us. There
is thus developing an ideology of science that I
would call a soteriology. The present-day ideol-
ogy of science is an ideology of salva-
tion. . . . Science alone holds the future to our
society. (TB, p. 182)
The basis on which technology is gaining power
over society is the power of those whose eco-
nomic position in society is strongest. Techno-
logical rationality today is the rationality of
domination. . . . These adverse effects, however,
should not be attributed to the internal laws of
technology itself but to its function within the
economy today. (p. 95) 6
Ellul radicalized the last comment a bit further and
said,
In earlier scientism, science thought that it could
suppress God and prove his nonexistence. But
this was true to only a minority. Today, this is not
a goal. . . . God serves no purpose in this situation
in which we now are. Science, thanks to ideol-
ogy, has now become divine as never before.
This is precisely the greatest danger. (TB, p. 184)
This difference concerning the prime mover of the
modern technological society has to do with
Marcuse’s focus on domination and Ellul’s emphasis
on absurdity. While Marcuse is concerned that citizens
of advanced industrial societies are dominated by the
system and deprived of their ability to be critical, Ellul
emphasized the absurdity created by the prevailing
techno-logical bluff. On the one hand, both notions de-
scribe a similar situation in which people think in the
way that the system wants them to think and, therefore,
do not enjoy their freedom. On the other hand, the
stress on the absurdity of the modern technological so-
ciety implies a more fundamental claim, namely, that
what is at stake here is not a class struggle between the
rich and the poor or the dominating and the dominated,
but being human—humanity itself. No individual and
no class are free from the techno-logical bluff, nor do
any of them benefit from it. The techno-logical bluff is
not produced by deliberate effort nor is it spread by
some specific action. It engenders a pseudoreligious
faith in technique, and the message can be preached in
These comments show there are differences in
Marcuse’s and Ellul’s approach to the similar phenom-
ena they observed. Whereas Marcuse lamented that
citizens of the advanced industrial society have lost the
ability to be critical, Ellul described the current situa-
tion that technique has become divine. The implica-
tion of this claim can be found already in TSoc. There
Ellul argued that human beings need a sense of mys-
tery on which one’s reason and consciousness is based.
Although technique destroys the mystery and does not
recognize the sacred, it eventually takes the place of
the sacred, as human beings cannot live without the
meaning that only the sacred can provide (TSoc,
p. 25). In TSys, Ellul described the same situation as a
technological system becoming a universe in which a
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin