Lesbian And Gay Marriage.pdf

(48 KB) Pobierz
<!DOCTYPE html PUBLIC "-//W3C//DTD HTML 4.01//EN" "http://www.w3.org/TR/html4/strict.dtd">
III. Feminist Theory and the Question of Lesbian and
Gay Marriage
For feminists, the question of lesbian and gay marriage is, or should be, inextri-
cably bound to the ongoing critique of marriage as an institution. That critique
originates in the theoretical and practical indictment of all social institutions, built
upon inequality and exclusion, which function as tools of male dominance. The
existing political movement to acquire marriage rights for lesbians and gays
appears to avoid this critique; instead, in the liberal political tradition, it seeks
simply to secure for gay and lesbian people the same legal rights that hetero-
sexual people enjoy.
In this article, I explore the question of lesbian and gay marriage through the
lens of feminist theory, first delineating briefly the feminist critique of marriage
as articulated historically and contemporarily. I then argue why it is necessary for
gays and lesbians to press for the right to marry: the second-class citizenship
created by the state’s differential treatment of gays and lesbians, I contend, is no
position from which to launch a viable challenge to the status quo. I intend here
to enrich the theoretical debate with practical considerations of the meaning of
inequality, and to enhance the social movement for lesbian and gay rights with
ideological insights from the feminist struggle. I write as a feminist, a lesbian, and
a thinker deeply concerned with the meanings of liberation on multiple fronts.
Feminist critiques of marriage have ranged from philosophers’ censure of
marriage as fostering gender inequality (Mill and Mill, 1970[1869]) to the free
lovers’ admonition that marriage shackles the human spirit (see D’Emilio and
Freedman, 1988). They comprise Emma Goldman’s (1970[1917]) assertion that
marriage makes woman a parasite at best, a prostitute at worst, and The
Feminists’ flamboyant actions rejecting this ‘inherently inequitable’ institution in
theory and practice (Echols, 1989: 176). They further include the radical feminist
Feminism & Psychology © 2004 SAGE (London, Thousand Oaks and New Delhi)
Vol. 14(1): 36–40; 0959-3535
DOI: 10.1177/0959-353504040300
854329665.006.png 854329665.007.png 854329665.008.png 854329665.009.png 854329665.001.png
 
Special Feature : BEVACQUA: The Question of Lesbian and Gay Marriage
37
view that marriage hampers women’s solidarity and attaches women to their
oppressors (Jones and Brown, 1968). While heterosexual, often married, women
issued most of these theoretical tracts, lesbian feminists were not silent on the
matter. Not only did lesbian feminists call for the eradication of marriage, they
also strongly suspected monogamy and emotional security as manifestations of
women’s oppression and male-identification (Radicalesbians, 1994[1970]).
Lesbian theorists have further questioned the assumption of heterosexuality as
normal and natural, and proposed instead that honest feminist analysis reveals the
many ways in which women are compelled to live heterosexual lives and to
marry (Rich, 1986[1980]). Recent work has investigated the tenacity of wedding
discourse in our shared cultural imagery, shedding light upon the $32 billion per
year US ‘wedding-industrial complex’ (Ingraham, 1999). This and other works
(Cott, 2000; Geller, 2001) have reinvigorated the feminist critique of marriage
and enhanced the current debate over lesbian and gay marriage rights.
For me, a lesbian feminist thinker and writer, the question of lesbian and gay
marriage is embedded in this theoretical and activist tradition. Some feminist
and progressive writers (e.g. Ettelbrick, 1997[1989]; Warner, 2000) argue that
marriage rights represent the assimilation of queer sexuality into a queer-hating
society, rendering us bland and colorless against a heterosexual landscape and
failing to liberate sexuality (Pierce, 1997[1995]). I argue instead that for any kind
of gay and lesbian social movement to make significant gains on our behalf, it
must make the removal of all formal inequalities a priority. The exclusion of a
portion of the population from a major social institution creates a second-class
citizenship for that group. This is a humiliating experience, whether as indi-
viduals we feel humiliated or not. Legalized same-sex marriage must be a prior-
ity for gay and lesbian activism. Rather than dismiss the pursuit of this right as so
much liberal reformism, feminist theorists must contend fully with the meaning
of exclusion for all people.
Two important questions accompany the issue of whether gays and lesbians
should have the right to marry. First, what are the privileged willing to do to make
this happen? Many of my heterosexual ‘allied’ friends are firm in their support
for this right, but I wonder what they are doing to make this legal change happen.
Are they willing to speak about it to all their constituents and lobby for political
change? Are they willing to refuse this very tangible privilege until it becomes
universal? Will the married among them obtain divorces until their circle opens
itself to all? Does ‘the personal is political’ continue to have meaning? In Peggy
McIntosh’s (1998[1988]) list of the privileges she enjoys based on having white
skin, none of the privileges are freely chosen. McIntosh no longer enjoys the
privilege of superior public schools for her children or drinking fountains
reserved for people with her skin color. Can it be more obvious that marriage is
a restricted club that heterosexual people publicly join in spite of its exclusionary
policies (Van Gelder, 1995[1984])? It is not enough for the oppressed to voice
their demands; the privileged play a crucial role in creating systemic change. The
task of these allies is first to recognize their own implication in heterosexist
854329665.002.png
38
Feminism & Psychology 14(1)
oppression and second to implement tactics of refusal, resistance, and publicity
to join the political project of sexual liberation.
My second question is, what will gays and lesbians do once we attain this
right? Pursuing a reform strategy is not a problem; thinking that all we need is a
reform strategy is. Once the right is achieved, are we going to embrace this
historically fraught, sexist institution wholeheartedly? Will we march ourselves
quickly to the trendiest department stores to register for expensive gifts and
get fitted for Vera Wang designer gowns, in preparation for our queen-for-a-day
nuptials? Will we squeal with joy at the sight of our friends’ rock-studded
engagement rings? Will we busy ourselves with bridal showers and honeymoon
vacations? I am afraid that is exactly what will happen, as it is happening already
among the commitment ceremony set. The institution of marriage, and the
wedding-industrial complex that supports it (Ingraham, 1999), will not dissolve
once gays and lesbians gain admission. The numerous benefits accompanying
marriage have been documented (e.g. Mohr, 1997[1995]) and are destined to out-
live the ban. But are these grounds for ongoing discrimination?
The attainment of the right to marry means that gays and lesbians will have to
decide for ourselves just how much we want to participate in supporting this insti-
tution. Radical feminists correctly theorized that marriage is built upon women’s
subordination and that there are no individual solutions to problems that are
shared collectively. Once same-sex marital rights are achieved, we can expect the
negative consequences for non-marriage among gays to resemble those for
heterosexuals currently. Single heterosexual mothers, particularly those who
receive public assistance, know full well that failure or refusal to marry carries a
price. Only sophisticated coalition politics will transform marriage.
Furthermore, it is not necessary to argue that ‘marriage is good,’ as have other
gay and lesbian writers (Eskridge, 1996; Sullivan, 1997; Graff, 1999), to advocate
for the right to marry. Indeed, 1970s US feminists did not have to argue that the
prospect of mandatory military service was ‘good’ when they supported passage of
the Equal Rights Amendment (ERA) guaranteeing women full equality under the
law. The fear of a gender-neutral draft fueled American doubts about the ERA. But
supporters could state that, with the ERA, women would have the same obligation
as men to consult their conscience about whether to comply with or resist the draft
(Williams, 1982). Equality was the ‘good’ they were seeking (the ERA failed to be
ratified). With same-sex marriage recognized as a legal right, both gays and
straights will have to grapple with the question of whether they will participate in a
fundamentally flawed institution and what they will do to change it.
Activist and writer Leslie Cagan (1999) describes an analogous issue from the
early-1990s. As a member of the movement for lesbian and gay liberation, and an
opponent of all forms of injustice, she supported the effort to remove the ban on
gays and lesbians in the US military. But as a leftist and longtime critic of
American military imperialism, implicated in much global mayhem and injustice,
she cannot help but carry this critique into all discussions of lifting the ban.
Rather than submit to single-minded, patriotic, pro-military fervor, she argues,
854329665.003.png
Special Feature : BEVACQUA: The Question of Lesbian and Gay Marriage
39
progressive lesbians and gays must call into question the very institution into
which we seek admission. In this article, I make a similar argument with respect
to marriage.
Some may read this as an expediency argument, one that sets aside moral (or
feminist) principle in the interest of pragmatism. Expediency arguments are
risky: for example, nineteenth-century woman suffragists in the US were willing
to play into the hands of southern racists in the hopes of attaining the vote by
urging the South to embrace (white) woman suffrage as a counterbalance to the
newly acquired black male vote (Davis, 1983). But feminists know that the
institution of marriage needs to be radically transformed to rid it of inequality or
abolished altogether (Fineman, 1995). Second-class citizens are in no position to
launch such a transformation. The mainstream population, along with policy
makers, can more easily dismiss the demands of the disenfranchised than of those
who possess full legal equality. Marriage rights belong on the lesbian and gay
agenda because, once we achieve equality of rights, the real work of liberation
can begin.
The feminist critique of marriage offers us a vision for radical transformation of
societal institutions. It forces us to think creatively about the problem and the
solution. The lesbian and gay agenda for liberation would do well to understand this
critique, honor it, and take it seriously. The path to liberation is a long one; in the
meantime, we need to work to dismantle those systems of inequality that treat us as
lesser human beings. Let us refuse the second-class citizenship we are handed by
challenging it head-on; but let us prepare for the larger battle at the same time.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
I wish to thank Cathryn Bailey for the many conversations that led me to write this essay.
REFERENCES
Cagan, L. (1999) ‘This Dyke’s a Leftie – This Leftie Is a Dyke’, in K. Kleindienst (ed.)
This Is What Lesbian Looks Like: Dyke Activists Take on the 21st Century , pp. 47–61.
Ithaca, NY: Firebrand.
Cott, N.F. (2000) Public Vows: A History of Marriage and the Nation . Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Davis, A.Y. (1983) Women, Race and Class . New York: Vintage, Random House.
D’Emilio, J. and Freedman, E.B. (1988) Intimate Matters: A History of Sexuality in
America . New York: Harper and Row.
Echols, A. (1989) Daring to Be Bad: Radical Feminism in America, 1967–1975 . Minne-
apolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Eskridge, W.N. (1996) The Case for Same-Sex Marriage: From Sexual Liberty to
Civilized Commitment . New York: The Free Press.
Ettelbrick, P.L. (1997[1989]) ‘Since When Is Marriage a Path to Liberation?’, in R.M.
854329665.004.png
40
Feminism & Psychology 14(1)
Baird and S.E. Rosenbaum (eds) Same-Sex Marriage: The Moral and Legal Debate ,
pp. 164–8. New York: Prometheus Books.
Fineman, M.A. (1995) The Neutered Mother, the Sexual Family, and Other Twentieth
Century Tragedies . New York: Routledge.
Geller, J. (2001) Here Comes the Bride: Women, Weddings, and the Marriage Mystique .
New York: Four Walls Eight Windows.
Goldman, E. (1970[1917]) The Traffic in Women and Other Essays . Ojai, CA: Times
Change Press.
Graff, E.J. (1999) What Is Marriage for? Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Ingraham, C. (1999) White Weddings: Romancing Heterosexuality in Popular Culture .
New York: Routledge.
Jones, B. and Brown, J. (1968) Toward a Female Liberation Movement . Boston, MA: New
England Free Press.
McIntosh, P. (1998[1988]) ‘White Privilege: Unpacking the Invisible Knapsack’, in P.S.
Rothenberg (ed.) Race, Class, and Gender in the United States: An Integrated Study
(4th edition ), pp. 165–9. New York: St Martin’s.
Mill, J.S. and Mill, H.T. (1970[1869]) Essays on Sex Equality . Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Mohr, R. D. (1997[1995]) ‘The Case for Gay Marriage’, in R.M. Baird and S.E. Rosen-
baum (eds) Same-Sex Marriage: The Moral and Legal Debate , pp. 84–104. New York:
Prometheus Books.
Pierce, C. (1997[1995]) ‘Gay Marriage’, in R.M. Baird and S.E. Rosenbaum (eds) Same-
Sex Marriage: The Moral and Legal Debate , pp. 169–79. New York: Prometheus
Books.
Radicalesbians (1994[1970]) ‘The Woman-Identified Woman’, in M. Schneir (ed.) Femi-
nism in Our Time: The Essential Writings, World War II to the Present , pp. 160–7.
New York: Vintage, Random House.
Rich, Adrienne (1986[1980]) ‘Compulsory Heterosexuality and Lesbian Existence’, in
Adrienne Rich (ed.), Blood, Bread, and Poetry , pp. 23–75. New York: W.W. Norton.
Sullivan, A. (ed) (1997) Same-Sex Marriage: Pro and Con . New York: Vintage, Random
House.
Van Gelder, L. (1995[1984]) ‘Marriage as a Restricted Club’, in A. Kesselman, L.D.
McNair and N. Schniedewind (eds) Women: Images and Realities, A Multicultural
Anthology , pp. 253–5. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield.
Warner, M. (2000) The Trouble with Normal: Sex, Politics, and the Ethics of Queer Life .
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Williams, W.W. (1982) ‘The Equality Crisis: Some Reflections on Culture, Courts, and
Feminism’, Women’s Rights Law Reporter 7: 175–200.
Maria BEVACQUA is Associate Professor and Chair of the Department of
Women’s Studies at Minnesota State University, Mankato, Minnesota, USA.
She is the author of Rape on the Public Agenda: Feminism and the Politics of
Sexual Assault (Northeastern University Press, 2000).
ADDRESS: Department of Women’s Studies, 109 Morris Hall, Minnesota State
University, Mankato, Minnesota 56001, USA.
[email: maria.bevacqua@mnsu.edu]
854329665.005.png
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin